Knowledge and Ideology in the Anthropocene

・26 min read

The Anthropocene seems to have a paradoxical relationship with knowledge.

On the one hand, it’s often describedE.g. in Lewis & Maslin (2018) and Harari (2015).

as the result of a centuries-long exponential growth of knowledge fuelled by investment: The interlocking feedback loops of capitalism and science – “the investment of profits to generate more profits, and the production of ever-greater knowledge from the scientific method”Lewis & Maslin (2018), 14

– have acted as “history’s chief engine for the past 500 years”Harari (2014), 306

and made “Homo sapiens […] a geological superpower”Lewis & Maslin (2018), 5

.

On the other hand, the Anthropocene is also seen as the result of a centuries-long lack of knowledge – the work of “a ‘humanity’ deficient in knowledge”Bonneuil & Fressoz (2016), 65

that unwittingly set “Earth on a new path in its long development”Lewis & Maslin (2018), 5

, characterised by climate and ecosystem breakdown. Climate scientists express this widespread view when they claim that “[w]e are the first generation with the knowledge of how our activities influence the Earth system”.Steffen et al. (2011), 757

Taken together, these narratives paint the picture of a civilisationThe globally integrated complex system that encompasses most of today’s societies, economies, cities and smaller social systems and their economic, political, military, diplomatic, social and cultural interactions.

that is in crisis because it was at the same time smart enough to exponentially increase its impact on the planet and too stupid to understand the consequences of that.Until recently, this has been more or less my own view; see the first section of my “Complexity, Metaphor and Radical Change”.

But this picture is misleading and dangerous. It wrongly models collective knowledge on a specific conception of of individual knowledge, distorts historical facts, obscures the true causal structure of our situation, and makes effective action in the face of our existential crisis less likely. Clearing up this misunderstanding will help us understand what really brought us into our current predicament – and how we can take steps beyond it.

Varieties of knowledge

So, what is knowledge?

Let’s start with our pre-philosophical, everyday understanding of it. The Oxford Dictionary of English begins its definition as follows: knowledge is “facts, information, and skills acquired through experience or education”.

There are two different types of knowledge in this definition:

The first type is also called propositional knowledge and is the mainstay of philosophical theories of knowledge. Textbook introductionsSee, e.g., Pritchard (2010).

usually spend a paragraph describing knowing how, another paragraph explaining why it’s derivative, and the remaining pages on knowing that.There are a few notable exceptions, first and foremost Ryle (1949).

This dominance rests on “the common assumption that reality has a propositional structure or, at least, that the proposition is the principal form in which reality becomes understandable to the human mind”.Zagzebski (1999)

Research into human perception and cognition suggests that this assumption is wrong.This argument has been made early on by Craik (1943), who states that thought’s “essential feature is not […] propositions but symbolism, and that this symbolism is largely of the same kind as that which is familiar to us in mechanical devices which aid thought and calculation.” Of course such a position has to be naturalistic, i.e. understand these questions as empirical ones.

On the most fundamental level, our brain makes sense of the world using generative or predictive models.For summaries of the research on predictive processing see e.g. Clark (2013) and Seth (2021).

Reality is just a causal constraint on these models.

Explicit and Implicit Models

A generative model

aims to capture the statistical structure of some set of observed inputs by tracking […] the causal matrix responsible for that very structure. A good generative model for vision would thus seek to capture the ways in which observed lower-level visual responses are generated by an interacting web of causes – for example, the various aspects of a visually presented scene.Clark (2013), 2

In other words, a generative model predicts the causes for what we perceive.

This can happen on multiple levelsSee Ramstead et al. (2019) for “a multiscale ontology of cognitive systems“, i.e. a framework for integrating accounts of systems on these different levels.

, from individual perception to scientific explanation: our brain tries to figure out (predicts) the objects and movements that cause our visual perception; a scientific model tries to figure out (predicts) the systems and processes, entities and laws that cause experimental observations.

From this perspective, a third type of knowledge appears to be more fundamental than the two we’ve encountered so far: knowledge of, or what the dictionary describes as “the theoretical or practical understanding of a subject”. We can now define this understanding more technically as having access to a generative model of a subject.

We get from knowledge of to knowledge that if we “think of models as entailing propositions”Bailer-Jones (2009), 186

: They are predictions about how our environment will behave, derived from explicit models. Explicit models are consciously articulated, interpretive descriptions of our environment, and we pay active attention to them in order to use them.

Knowing how is based on models, too – implicit models, in this case: non-conceptual, embodied representations of our environment that we use unconsciously. Implicit models are at the heart of every skill; their embodiment can consist in practices, habits, instincts, and all other parts of our phenotype, from basic body structure to hairstyles, from language to calluses.In this respect, it corresponds to what Polanyi (1966) called tacit knowledge. Holland (1995, 33) takes up this label to “distinguish two kinds of internal models, tacit and overt. A tacit internal model simply prescribes a current action, under an implicit prediction of some desired future state, as in the case of the bacterium. An overt internal model is used as a basis for explicit, but internal, explorations of alternatives, a process often called lookahead.” This distinction is co-extensive to the one made here.

In other words, “an agent does not have a model of its world – it is a model”. Friston,(2013), 213 (my emphasis)

Take a fish as an example: its body “can be considered to be an implicit model of the fluid dynamics and other affordances of its watery environment.”Seth (2015), 6

If we think about models in this way, it becomes clear that every system is a model of its environment – at least every stable system that survives in its environment (which is the type of system we’re usually interested in).ibid., 156

This holds for all scales, from single cells and organisms to, importantly, social systems:Ramstead et al. (2019).

a team models its organisational environment, a company models its market situation, a civilisation models the world it inhabits.

This requires us to rethink what collective knowledge is: It is not the aggregation or collective adoption of individual knowledge, of explicit models available to individual attention and expressed in books, papers, and databases. It is access to explicit and implicit models at the level of the collective – the models social systems have of their environment.

Technology and Techne

Explicit collective models are realised as technology. We can think of technology as “a programming of phenomena to our purposes”, a “purposed system”.Arthur (2009). This understanding resonates with Heidegger’s view of technology as the practice of turning everything into a means: “Everything approaches us merely as a source of energy or as something we must organize.” (Blitz 2014)

This gives us a usefully broad scope of the concept, including entities like “monetary systems, contracts, symphonies, and legal codes, as well as physical methods and devices”.Arthur (2009)

Technology is combinatorial (technologies are combinations of existing components) and recursive (these components are themselves technologies).ibid.

As a result, the models realised in any higher technology (that combines more basic technologies) cannot be held individually anymore:

[T]echnology becomes a complex of interactive processes—a complex of captured phenomena— supporting each other, using each other, “conversing” with each other, “calling” each other much as subroutines in computer programs call each other. The “calling” […] is ongoing and continuously interactive.ibid.

It is therefore collective actors (i.e. social systems) who hold the models: teams, institutions, communities, industries, economies, civilisations – depending on the recursion level and timeframe under consideration, and on whether we look at an individual technology or bodies of technology (from specific domains to technology as a whole). But all of these technologies “are developed not by a single practitioner or a small group of these, but by a wide number of interested parties.”ibid.

So technology is what social systems collectively design, use and pay attention to, from electricity and electronics to meetings and markets, to realise their purpose. It thus contains one end of a spectrum of social practices: “explicitly coordinated behavior that is rule-governed, intentional, voluntary”.Haslanger (2018), 235

At the other end of this spectrum are

patterns in behavior that are the result of shared cultural schemas or social meanings that have been internalized through socialization and shape […] cognition, affect, and experience.ibid.

Taken together, social meanings – from concepts like nation, race, and gender to scripts for behaviour in specific social situations – and “skills for interpretation, interaction and coordination that we exercise ‘unthinkingly’”ibid., 158

constitute a cultural technēA term coined by Haslanger (2017, 2018, 2019, 2021).

:

a network of social meanings, tools, scripts, schemas, heuristics, principles, and the like, which we draw on in action, and which gives shape to our practices”Haslanger (2017), 155

These are “the sources of our practical orientations, that is, the social preconditions for thinking and acting”Haslanger (2019), 11

– and, a fortiori, the foundation technology rests upon. A cultural technē thus realises the implicit model of a social system: the “part of a system that functions […] to regulate our interactions in a domain”ibid., 156

.

Just as an individual implicit model emerges from the interactions of a biological system’s components, a social system’s collective implicit model emerges from the interactions of its components, from people and artefacts to ideas and institutions.This conceptualisation of social systems is close to DeLanda’s Assemblage Theory (DeLanda 2005). I regard the of kinds of things just named as equally real, but ultimately existing as patterns in a high-dimensional state space. See my “From Predictive Processing to Topological Thinking: Prolegomena to a Future Paradigm”.

It is not an achievement of conscious individual action or an aggregation of individual models, but an emergent property of the larger system.

We can now map out the varieties of knowledge we have found in the following way:

Individual Collective
Explicit Knowing That Technology
Implicit Knowing How Cultural Technē

Types of knowledge

We can use this map to help us understand why our civilisation is in crisis – and to expose what is just a smokescreen explanation for this fact.

Our Failing World Model

Collective knowledge on the civilisational level is our civilisation’s (explicit and implicit) model of its environment (“the world”). A model that has been quite useful, judging from humanity’s evolutionary success in terms of growth, spread, and environmental transformation.See Lewis & Maslin (2018) for a history of this impact.

(This is the perspective of the “growth of knowledge enables the Anthropocene” narrative.)

Of course today we see that it is exactly growth, spread, and environmental transformation that massively threaten our survival as a civilisation (and possibly as a species).See Servigne & Stevens (2020) for an overview.

This suggests that the impact of these phenomena on the Earth System and thus on our collective future is not tracked in our civilisation’s model of the world; otherwise it would behave differently. (This what the “lack of knowledge enables the Anthropocene” narrative highlights.)

In other words, our model of the world is failing.

The most common hypothesis why it is failing is this: Humans just can’t comprehend complex systems, nonlinear change, and long causal chains because they’re not evolutionary equipped for that – it wasn’t necessary in our original cognitive niche.

This is the standard answer of the frustrated scientist, and the one I have accepted for a long time.See, e.g., “Complexity, Metaphor and Radical Change”.

But it is fundamentally flawed: It assumes that our civilisation’s collective model (the one that is failing) amounts to the collective adoption of individual models (the ones that are constrained by our cognitive capacities) – and we have just seen that this is not the case.

The Famous World3 Model

For an illustration, consider the famous “World3 Model”. It describes interactions between world population, industrial growth, food production and limits in ecosystems, and provided the foundation for the influential 1972 Club of Rome report The Limits to Growth. It’s an (explicit) individual model that shows what’s apparently missing from our civilisation’s (implicit) collective one: that we’re part of a giant, growth-producing feedback loop that we have to stop to avoid overshoot and collapse.

The Equally Famous Iceberg Model

But why has it not been adopted and changed our collective behaviour in the 50 years since its conception, replacing our failing model? That was the explicit goal of Dennis and Donella Meadows and their collaborators when they initially proposed it: to replace an inadequate, reductionist model of the world with a better, holistic one. Donella Meadows describes this strategy in her famous Iceberg Model: the point of greatest leverage to change a system’s behaviour, she contends, is shifting the mental models that shape it.

Talking of mental models in this context points to the heart of the problem, though: Meadows’s strategy disregards how collective knowledge is actually realised – a social system’s model is an emergent result of its components’ interactions, not the collective adoption of explicit individual models. In effect, she’s trying to replace an emergent collective model with the collective adoption of an individual one – which will fail, however much effort one puts into its promotion.That might be one of the reasons why Meadows changed her tune slightly in Meadows (1999). There she describes societal paradigms, “shared social agreements about the nature of reality” (Meadows 1999, 18), still very much as models that can be made explicit and changed by influential actors like Copernicus or Einstein. But beyond that she now recognises a need to transcend paradigms altogether, which – while still portrayed as an individual activity (ibid. 19) – is quite close to the therapeutic approach towards ideology described below.

This brings us back to the question, which we can now put more precisely: Why is our emergent collective model of the world, realised in (social and material) technology and, more fundamentally, our cultural technē, failing?

Ideological Oppression

Quite simply because “a cultural technē can go wrong”Haslanger (2021), 28

: It can become an ideology that distorts and hides aspects of the world the perception of which would question or threaten the existing social order.This conception of ideology follows Haslanger (2017, 2018, 2021) and goes back to Althusser and the Marxist understanding of ideology as false consciousness.

This leads us to an alternative hypothesis about why our model fails: because it is ideologically captured and distorted.

Far from being incapable of insight into complex systems, people have made alarming predictions about the trajectory of our current civilisation as early as the 18th century. So it was possible to develop and promote adequate explicit models of our world – but they have been consistently marginalised by ideological oppression.See Bonneuil & Fressoz (2016).

Ideological oppression is an emergent property of the complex system that is our civilisation: a product of the dominant incentive system, and a set of systemic constraints on individual behaviour.See Juarrero (1999) for an account of how constraints have “downward” causal power.

It is so effective because it is widely invisible – “we typically embody a practice before we even know we are engaged in it”.Haslanger (2021), 27

As a mechanism, it works like this: Adhering to and amplifying the dominant ideology promises individual benefits (wealth, power, status) while deviation is threatened with punishment (exclusion, loss of status). This shifts dispositions in ideology’s favour and constrains behaviour in a way that is useful to the wider system, i.e. the civilisation the ideology stabilises, without needing to resort to more dramatic measures like physical violence.

In our case, ideology bends individual behaviour towards extraction and consumption. A growth- and innovation-based system like ours uses these strategies in two interlocking feedback loops:On the first feedback loop, see Harari (2014) and Lewis & Maslin (2018); on the second, Jackson (2017).

growth enables investment, which increases innovation and productivity, which enable further growth and reduce the need for labour, which necessitates growth on pain of economic collapse. Extraction provides the resources to feed these loops, while consumption provides the demand to drive them.

Capitalism’s Growth Loops

And in fact, our civilisation has been so successful evolutionarily, out-growing and displacing almost all other civilisations, because it is the most extractive and the most innovative at the same time: When resources are abundant, the most extractive culture will be dominant, and innovation has made sure resources stay abundant.I will expand on this argument in a future essay.

Ideology can therefore be described on two levels:

On the level of the system, i.e. our civilisation, extractive and consumerist ideology emerge from this evolutionary process as implicit strategies that constrain the behaviour of institutions, humans and other system components in the service of maximising overall growth and thus dominance.

On the level of interactions between the components, extractive and consumerist ideology are a cultural technē captured and distorted by the interests of institutions, humans and other system components that profit from its current configuration.

These descriptions lead to a very different conclusion than the “we’re just too stupid” argument: We’re not too stupid to keep our civilisation out of crisis, we’re too self-interested and blinded by ideology, in the service of a growth-addicted, extractive wider system that we create and that constrains us. We’re not missing cognitive capabilities, but the space to unfold them without ideological constraints.

What to Do

What we need to win this space is not more individual knowledge, but the collective knowledge how to disrupt and transform ideology: social technology to change our cultural technē. Three main components of this social technology are critical theory, social movements, and alternative institutions.This is similar how Erik Olin Wright describes the tasks of emancipatory social science: “elaborating a systematic diagnosis and critique of the world as it exists; envisioning viable alternatives; and understanding the obstacles, possibilities, and dilemmas of transformation” (Wright 2010, 10). Of course the latter two need to be translated into strategic action.

Critical Theory

Critical theory is situated theory that supports the emancipatory struggle of the (ideologically) oppressed from within a social movement. As part of this endeavour and to help open a thinking space without (or at least less) ideological constraints, it delivers a moral, epistemic and ontological critique of ideology.

Critical theory enables the articulation, discussion and moral assessment of problematic social relations previously masked by ideology. It thus helps processes like consciousness raising produce normative knowledgeHaslanger (2021), 56. Note her clarification on the status of normative knowledge: “What I say here is compatible with a robust moral realism, a quietist or deflationary moral realism, moral constructivism, and some forms of moral anti-realism”.(Haslanger 2017, 165) For my own take on this, see “Is there such a thing as moral truth?”

, which ideally leads to new or reformed norms around these relations. Examples are the MeToo movement and how it changed norms around acceptable male behaviour or, more fundamental, the emergence of intersectional feminism and how it reframed questions of social position.

In addition, “changes to the epistemic practices are required in order to loosen the grip of ideology”Haslanger (2021), 55

. Part of this epistemic critique is emancipatory conceptual engineering. It tries to wrangle concepts from ideology and give them more useful meanings, e.g. by “debunk[ing] naturalistic accounts of race and reveal[ing] race to be socially constructed”Haslanger (2018), 231

.

An ontological critique of ideology defends the reality of social systems and structures against reductionism and methodological individualism and provides a toolkit to expose ideological assumptions and positsFor realist social ontologies see e.g. Haslanger (2019) and DeLanda (2005). Cf. also my “From Predictive Processing to Topological Thinking: Prolegomena to a Future Paradigm”.

. Frameworks like the “implicit model as cultural technē” one proposed here can bridge the gap between ontological and epistemic critique.

A prerequisite for the practice of participatory critical theory are spaces where the oppressed can articulate and examine their experiences without the framing of the oppressing system, even in its well-meaning, “supportive” guise. These spaces can only be created by social movements and alternative institutions, which can in turn be supported and legitimised by critical theory.

Examples for critical theory include Sally Haslanger’s conceptual engineeringHer most influential work in this regard is probably Haslanger (2000).

, Critical Race TheoryFor an overview see Delgado & Stefancic (2001).

, Bonneuil & Fressoz’s account of the Anthropocene discourseBonneuil & Fressoz (2016)

, and Mitchell & Chaudhury’s critique of white apocalyptic thinkingMitchell & Chaudhury’s (2020)

.

Social Movements

Social movements are concerted efforts by large groups of people to demand and promote social change. They “intervene in material conditions”Haslanger (2018), 231

and try to effect the desired change by one or more of three pathways:

All three pathways ideally lead to both direct and indirect results: They make harmful or oppressive behaviours and strategies less attractive or even untenable, promote alternatives to these behaviours, and undermine the invisibility and legitimacy of the dominant ideology.

Successful movements connect what people already care about with a larger cause and enable them to experience self-determination in a collective effort. This creates experiences of agency and choice and thus sets the stage for changing social technē via critique and alternative institutions.

Examples of successful social movements include the suffragettes, the Indian independence movement, the Civil Rights movement, Otpor, and the LGBT rights movement.

Alternative Institutions

The third component is “building alternative institutions and deliberately fostering new forms of social relations that embody emancipatory ideals”Wright (2010), 324

, thus changing our cultural technē and over time civilisation itself.

Alternative institutions include People’s Assemblies, Universal Basic Income, mutual aid networks, and complementary, e.g. local or community currencies. They work outside the current system’s consumption/extraction loops and range from small-scale practices for collaborative decision-making to large-scale socio-economic arrangements.

There are three different pathways how such institutions can fundamentally change the current system. Two of them work bottom-up in an either revolutionary or evolutionary way:

first, by altering the conditions for eventual rupture, and second, by gradually expanding the effective scope and depth of their operations so that capitalist constraints cease to impose binding limits.ibid, 328

A third pathway involves “engaging the state, using it to further the process of emancipatory social empowerment”ibid., 336

in a process of system transformation rather than replacement.

Our civilisation is a complex system, and we can’t predict the influence alternative institutions will have on it. Therefore either of these approaches needs to start with experiments of limited scope that can be scaled up if successful (which is exactly how proponents of People’s Assemblies and Universal Basic Income are approaching the issue).

All of these approaches also need to take into account that they are competing not only with specific institutions, but through their connections with and embeddedness in other social systems with a whole set of arrangements (a global civilisation) that has successfully displaced almost all alternatives because it is the most extractive and the most innovative at the same time.

Short of global revolution or collapse, alternative institutions will only be successful in such a competition if they can siphon resources from the existing arrangements into experiments and exploit existing institutions to scale the successful ones. They have to extract resources from an extractive system to outcompete its components, which can happen in one of two ways:

They can introduce effective resource constraints (without tipping the global system into collapse) which change the selection criteria for civilisations in favour of more resource-efficient ones; or they can create new sources of abundance, e.g. through regenerative practices, which enable them to outcompete the current regime under the same selection criteria, but with different resources.

For simple thermodynamic reasons, a shift in energy sources or material technologies will not suffice; there needs to be a fundamental change in social technologies and, first and foremost, our cultural technē. In essence, we need to find and adopt non-material sources of abundance:

[O]n today’s evidence, technologizing our way out of this does not look likely. […] [T]he only solution left to us is to change our behavior, radically and globally, on every level. In short, we urgently need to consume less. A lot less. And we need to conserve more. A lot more. Emmott (2013), 184–186

What we therefore need are paradoxical memes: Ideologies and institutions that can, promoted and prefigured by social movements, outcompete extractive counterparts by opposing and reversing extraction.

Emancipatory Social Technology

If all three components – theory, movements, institutions – are working and mutually reinforcing, we have the knowledge we need: a working and resilient social technology to change our cultural technē.

And we can finally start stepping out of the trap that is the Anthropocene.

References

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Harley McDonald-Eckersall, Gregor Groß and Phil Harvey for comments on drafts of this essay.