We all are trying to make sense of the world. For that, we implicitly
or explicitly use frameworks: scaffolding in the form of
conceptual spaces, ontologies, models, and theories that guide our
perceptions, judgements, and predictions – and that can be more or less
useful.Examples for generic sensemaking frameworks are Dave
Snowden’s Cynefin and Cynthia Kurtzs’s Confluence framework. The Product
Field is a domain-specific sensemaking framework.
Three Criteria and a Strategy
A sensemaking framework is more useful
- the wider its scope of applicability, i.e. the greater its generality,
- the more detail and distinction it can accommodate and help process in specific situations, and
- the less cognitive capacity is needed to use it.
While a framework is clearly better the higher it scores
in all dimensions, wide scope/high detail/low load frameworks
being the ones to look for, in reality these dimensions stand in
tension with each other: Often a general framework that allows
for a lot of detail is complicated and cognitively demanding; a general
and easy-to-use framework usually allows for little detailed insight;
and in most instances, a detail-rich framework can only cover a narrow
scope if it is to stay comprehensible.The mentioned frameworks fall into the “general and
easy-to-use” (Cynefin and Confluence) and “detail rich, narrow scope”
(Product Field) categories.
A framework can score high in all three dimensions if it provides abstractions that can be used in a fractal manner:
- A small set of highly general concepts, applied and connected in a way that
- enables the description of order on different levels of abstraction, enhancing detail, and
- reveals similar patterns across these levels, reducing cognitive load.
Visualising these abstractions and embodying them in practice further reduces cognitive load by employing more cognitive capacities in parallel, while the incorporation of different senses and sensibilities reduces bias and increases input and thus available detail.
The following framework applies these strategies.
A Proposed Implementation
Theories about empirical reality (that exhibit an
ought-relation from world to judgement – our judgements should conform
to the world) work on different levels of abstraction, the “right” level
for a given set of phenomena being the one where a theory provides a
maximum of explanatory and predictive scope and detail. That is the case
when a theory’s model of relationships between (atomic and emergent)
components and attributes of a system delivers maximum
informationSee Hoel (2017) and his concept of “causal
emergence”.
about the system when compared to other descriptions.
A very abstract ontology based on systems that live in state
spacesAn example for such an ontology is Deleuze’s abstract
process ontology in the interpretation of DeLanda (2002).
is our best framework for describing the most fundamental
level – “what there is” Quine (1948); contra Quine, this is a realist
ontology!
. Everything in the universe, from subatomic particles to
galaxy clusters, from emotions to economic systems, can in principle be
understood and explained by causal and/or mathematical models based on
and constrained by this ontologyFor a proposal of a theory based on such an ontology
that describes models on multiple levels see Hesp et al. (2019) and in
general that work around Karl Friston’s Free Energy Principle.
– including how and why these models and explanations
have to be criticised. This maximises generality.
Within that framework, specific models describe specific regions of
the universe with varying scope and detail. On a physical level,
M-theory is as much such a model as were Newtonian physics or Platonic
geometry.Through this lens, the “unreasonable effectiveness of
mathematics” (Wigner 1960) becomes as un-mysterious as the prevalence of
specific mathematical tools, like group theory, in modern theoretical
physics: At its core, theoretical physics is an increasingly abstract
description of increasingly intricate patterns in an
increasingly large state space. Also, the specifics of these models and
the accompanying theories suddenly become much less interesting if they
are not expected to provide an ontology themselves anymore, but are only
concretisations of it.
On other levels of abstraction, looking at wider and more
complex systems, a neurophysiological explanation has more causal
information (scope and detail) about brain structure or behaviour than a
physical one; a memetic explanation of the ascendance of consumer
capitalism might have more causal information than a historical one.
All of these systems can be represented in state spaces, modelling their emergent behaviour as following specific attractors determined by the interactions of their components. This means high score for generality, and provides potential for visualisation. From this approach, we can derive several fractal abstractions, for example:
- Markov Blankets and System Boundaries
- Causal Emergence and Levels of Abstraction
- Attractors and Attractor Landscapes
- Selection and Self-organisation
- Perception and action as reductions of surprise
Explicit or implicit moral theories (that exhibit an
ought-relation from judgement to world – the world should
conform to our judgements) are a different type of theory – they don’t
(aim to) describe reality, but are constructive solutions to practical
problems.See “Is there such a thing as moral truth?”
At the same time, we value in them the same qualities as
in empirical theories: scope, specificity and ease-of-use.
Moral theories are developed and checked for validity (or usefulness)
not from a third-, but from a first-person perspectiveSee “Perspectives”
, which itself (and with it the emergence of normativity)
can be explained by an empirical, more specifically an evolutionary
theorySeen again Hoel (2017). For another non-reductionist
evolutionary account see Deacon (2011).
. This increases the latter’s generality and makes moral
theories part of the overall framework.
Every theory is necessarily developed, judged and disseminated from a first-person perspective and in a specific social context. This perspective must be reflected on and, if necessary, criticised when making moral judgements, i.e. constructing solutions to practical problems. Not reflecting on this perspective or taking an explicit moral stance towards the context means implicitly taking an affirmative stance towards it. This highlights the importance of critical, e.g. feminist or post-colonialist theories.
With this framework, we get a non-reductionist naturalism that
includes seemingly un-naturalistic perspectives without giving up on
(and instead explaining) their normative power.Overall, this proposal can be read as an updated and
rephrased version of a Sellarsian “fusion” of the Scientific and the
Manifest Image (Sellars 1962).
It uses fractal abstractions on different levels of
abstraction to increase generality and specificity while reducing
cognitive load.
References
- Deacon, T. W. (2011), Incomplete Nature: How Mind Emerged from Matter
- DeLanda, M. (2002), Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy
- Hesp, S., et al. (2019), “A Multi-scale View of the Emergent Complexity of Life: A Free-Energy Proposal”
- Quine, W. V. O. (1948), “On What There Is”, The Review of Metaphysics 2 (5), 21–38
- Hoel, E. P. (2017), “Agent above, atom below. How agents causally emerge from their underlying microphysics”
- Sellars, W. (1962), “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man”, in Colodny, R. (ed.),: Science, Perception, and Reality, 35-78
- Wigner, E. P. (1960): “The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences”, Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13 (1), 1–14
Acknowledgements
I’m grateful to Phil Harvey for comments on a draft of this essay.